Induction Universals Particulars

What is it?

An attempt to explicate the relationship between inductive reasoning and the philosophical discourse regarding universals.

Following on from a discussion regarding the role of universals in Hume’s account of causation. This, and the realisation that Hume’s causation involves an inductive move from particular regularity observations to a general causal statement, led me to wonder about the relationship between the universals debate and a descriptive account of inductive reasoning. Someone else has probably already pointed out the connection but I wanted to work through it myself anyway.

Some sources

Lipton - Inference to the best explanation - Contains some detailed discussion of induction. Garrett - What is this thing called metaphysics? - Source for general positions in the universals debate. Hume - An enquiry concerning human understanding. - Source for Hume’s views.

Induction

First let’s try to give a fairly general account of inductive reasoning: - observe a.1 - observe a.2 - … - observe a.n - Therefore, always A. In the above account A must refer in some way to a similarity between elements of the set a = [ A 1, … , a.n].

Attributing Similarity

So we are in a situation in which we want to describe how we come to an understanding of the simmilarities in a that allows us to make the move to talking in terms of A. For the sake of argument, I will assume here that the determination of these simmilarities is unproblematic (even though this may not necessarily be the case).

What philosophical mechanisms could be employed to account for these simmilarities? The possibilities are those put forward in the debate over the existence of universals. This leads to the postulation of three main strategies: - i) One could account for the simmilarities by arguing that there are one or more universals instantiated in the elements of a. - ii) One could argue along traditional nominalist lines (e.g. one could argue for a general class that would account for the simmilarities of a). - iii) One could employ trope theory to argue that the members of a are actually made up of bundles of abstract particulars and that the simmilarities observed between some of these bundles have their basis in semantics rather than ontology.

Problems

The problems that arise for the above possibilities are just those that arise for them in more general discussions of the similarity problem. Namely, the universals view can fall victim to criticism on the basis that it entails an infinite-regress of universals; the standard nominalist views seem to imply the existence of some other universal (e.g. class-membership); finally, the trope theory view fails to give a coherent account of how these abstract particulars are bundled together into objects.

Conclusions

I think it has been fairly conclusively demonstrated above that any descriptive account of inductive reasoning is inextricably linked to considerations regarding the existence of universals (or more generally, how we account for simmilarities). The plausibility of the trope theory view might indicate that a move away from ontologically-based simmilarity and towards a linguistic one could be fruitful when developing a descriptive account of inductive reasoning.

Upon further consideration, it seems that we are in the following situation: - Any descriptive account of induction needs to explain how we move from talk of particular events to talk of general similarities between those events. - If such an explanation requires an ontological commitment, then further difficulties arise regarding how we move from the semantic to the ontological (see my note on modified Carnap below). - If however, such an explanation only requires a semantic commitment, all one need do is provide an account of how such commitments are arrived at.

Further Work Needed

Chris Wilcox

orpeth.com